Bibliographies and reviews | |||||
Grading | Nationality | Population registers | Race | Minorities | Suicide |
John Dower on "race" and "nationality"
"Legal Perspectives" on territoriality and nationality
First posted 12 April 2008
Last updated 23 June 2011
Dower 1986
•
Yamato race
|
"natives" and "Japanese" as "nationality"
Dower 1999
•
"Korea, Taiwan (also known as Formosa)"
|
gaichi or "dependency", naichi or "metropolitan Japan"
Selected topics
•
Interior and Exterior jurisdictions
This review is a springboard for examining the continuing importance -- six decades after Chosenese and Taiwanese lost their Japanese nationality in 1952 -- of the territorial foundations of Japanese nationality.
John W. Dower | |||||||||||||||||
1986 1999 |
War Without Mercy: Race and Power in the Pacific War Japan in War and Peace: Selected Essays
New York: New Press, 1993 (hardcover), 1995 (paper cover) Embracing Defeat: Japan in the Wake of World War II | ||||||||||||||||
These three books -- especically the 1986 and 1999 works -- are major contributions to the English literature on World War II in Asia and the Pacific. However, their readability and apparent credibility have led many researchers to suppose that Dower knew more than he did about some of the topics he touched on in passing -- like Japan's postwar Constitution, nationality and naturalization, and ethnic, racial, and other minorities. The popularity of Dower's racialization of the war and its aftermath have significantly inspired other writers to impute race and racism to Japan's policies and laws, concerning "Koreans" and other vaguely defined minorities in Japan, before, during, and after the Pacific War. For sure, not few earlier writers addressed "racial" attitudes, but Dower's books appear to me to have inspired what I would call a "fashion" of racialization. Biographical noteJohn Dower was a professor of Japanese studies at the University of California in San Diego when War Without Mercy was published in 1986. By 1999 when Embracy Defeat came out, he was a professor of history at the Massachusettes Institute of Technology, needs little further introduction. Both of these books, which received numerous awards, became virtual bestsellers among publications on Pacific War and the postwar Occupation of Japan. Dower's influence on younger scholars has been enormous. Many writers on social issues in Japan have adopted his views, expressed in both books, Dower 1986Yamato raceChapter 1, Patterns of a Race War, begins with an overview of mainly "Western racial fears" of the "Asian racial dreams" evident in the "Pan-Asianism" of the Greater East Asia Co-Posperity Sphere. Japan's seemingly oppressive actions in East Asia and the Pacific, before and after Pearl Harbor, inspired various reactions from critics.
Dower speaks of "the blatant racism of the Nazis" (page 4) and of the "racist underpinnings of the European and American colonial structure" (page 5)" -- whereas Japan "did not invade independent countries in southern Asia" but only "colonial outposts which the Westerners had dominated for generations, taking abolutely for granted their racial and cultural superiority over their Asian subjects" (page 5). Some critics, Dower says, saw Japan's actions in Asia as those of a fascist state. Some regarded them more as the desperate ambitions of a latecomer to regional imperialism. Yet others thought they reflected "a racial supremacism as virulent in its own way as the master-race theories of the Nazis" (Dower 1986, page 8). Having raised the spectre of "master-race", Dower immediately segues to the following paragraph and endnote (page 8, and note 7, page 320, underscoring mine).
Japan had no "citizens" then or now. Then people with Japanese nationality were "subjects" (shinmin) and "nationals" (kokumin). Today Japan has only "nationals" (kokumin). The United States, then as now, had "citizens" and "nationals", which were different statuses of people who possessed US nationality. Under the domestic laws of both Japan and the United States, "nationality" referred to the civil status recognized in international law as affiliation with a state, regardless of race. Japanese domestic laws did not define race or discriminate on account of race, while some US federal, state, and local codes treated people differently according to their putative race. Throughout his book, however, Dower uses all manner of words -- citizen, nation, nationality, people, race, state -- with practically no glossing of their meanings in Japanese. One gets glimples in the transliterations of the titles of Japanese sources in the endnotes, but there is little attempt in the main text to differentiate what words that, however similar they may appear to be in some contexts, are not the same. Two-thirds into the main text, "Yamato race" is finally glossed as "Yamato minzoku" (page 205). Not until Chapter 10 -- "Global Policy with the Yamato Race as Nucleus" -- does he, as promised in the above cited endnote, discuss at length the word "minzoku", and this is what he says (page 267, underscoring mine).
According to an endnote, the title of the work from which Dower digests the distinctions between "minzoku" and "jinshu" in Japaneses "Yamato Minzoku o Chūkaku to suru Sekai Seisaku no Kentō [An Investigation of Global Policy with the Yamato Race as Nucleus]" (Chapter 10, note 1, page 357). Apparently, though, Dower is not himself moved to distinguish between what was "race" as a narrow biological concept, and what was "race" as a broader anthropological and even political notion. And one of the major flaws of Dower's otherwise impressive book is precisely that he imputes more to "race" than the "race" metaphor deserves. Dower talks about "race relations" and "patterns of racial . . . thinking" (page 12), and "racial and racist ways of thinking" (page 13), apparently differentiating between "racial" and "racist" -- but he does not elaborate on what constitutes "racist" as opposed to "racial" thinking. Does his own speaking of "the Japanese" constitute a "racial" label for those he considers the "people" of Japan as a matter of "race"? Dower describes the way the door was closed to Asian immigration under the "quota" system introduced in 1924. Here describes the setting of quotas for each "nationality" as two percent of the population of the nations resident in the United states in 1920, but narrow door was "closed to Asians (as well as Arabs)". The quota law also stipulated, he said, that "no one could enter the United States as a permanent resident who was not eligible to become a naturalized citizen, and under prior regulations Asians already had been designated ineligible for naturalization" -- referring to fact that "the naturalization law amounted to a pure 'color' law" (page 164). Dower exaggerates. The so-called "Immigration Act of 1924" did not forbid the entry as permanent residents of aliens not allowed to naturalize. It provided, in fact, that "No alien ineligible to citizenship shall be admitted to the United States unless such alien . . ." -- and proceeded to list several exceptions. And indeed a number of aliens "ineligible to citizenship" continued to be admitted to the United States as non-quota immigrants -- including some Japanese nationals. While clear that US naturalization codes had been racist from their inception in the late 18th century shortly after the founding of the United States -- to say nothing of the rulings in numerous court cases, some of which Dower cites -- as "color" laws they were far from "pure". Had they been pure, all manner of people who were not categorically "white" in the view of US laws and the courts would have been barred from naturalization. Dower goes on to review how, during the war with Japan, United States abrogated its Chinese exclusion laws, and allowed a handful of Chinese to come to the United States, since the United States and China were allies in a war that arguably started because of the manner in which the United States, with Great Britain and the Netherlands, had supported China's cause against Japan after Japan's military hijacking of China's state in the late 1930s. And he makes it clear that "the European and American colonial structure" -- far more than Japan, which had colonized only Korea and Formosa -- had "suppressed independence in most of Asia" (page 167). Yet not once does Dower disclose that, while the United States was closing its doors to immigration from Asia, and legally banning the naturalization of Asian immigrants, and while some states were barring interracial marriages, Japan imposed no racial restrictions on entry to the country and legally facilitated access to its nationality, through marriage and adoption in 1873, and also through naturalization from 1899 -- with no racial restrictions whatever. And during the decades of the late 19th and early 20th century -- while Asians including Japanese, Chinese, and Indians were regarded as "ineligible to citizenship" under US naturalization laws -- some Chinese, Indians, and nationals of other countries were becoming Japanese. "It was not that the Japanese people were, in actuality, homogeneous and harmonious, devoid of individuality and thoroughly subordinated to the group," Dower observes, "but rather that the Japanese ruling groups were constantly exhorting them to become so" (page 31). He speaks of Japan as "a race and nation" in the eyes of "most Europeans and Americans" (page 38), and the perception in the United States of "the Japanese enemy" as not just the "enemy's armed forces" but in terms of "the Japanese as a race and culture" (page 53). He cites Admiral Halsey's call for "the almost total elimination of the Japanese as a race" (page 55), and remarks that public opinion in both the United Kingdom and the United States demanded, "if not the extermination of the Japanese people" then certainly the country's thorough defeat (page 55). He talks about the "national and racial destiny" of "the Japanese people" (page 56) and "national psychology" (page 57), and "national psychosis" (page 129) Racial world viewDower's conflation of "race" and "nation" is evident throughout the book when one examines usage in his Japanese sources. One of many cases in point would be the following characterization of a magazine article published immediately after the beginning of the Pacific War (page 211, and note 17, page 350, underscoring mine.
Ōgushi Toyoo (大串兎代夫 1903-1967), a regular contributor to the magazine, was both a legal scholar and a Ministry of Education official. He was deeply involved in the ministry's "National Spiritual Culture Institute" (国民精神文化研究所 Kokumin Seishin Bunka Kenyōjo), which as its name implies promoted research on the spiritual culture of nationals (国民 kokumin). Purged from public office after the war, he returned to his legal roots, as an attorney and professor of law. Founded in 1932, the Nationality Spiritual Culture Institute, via wartime mergers with other agencies and postwar transformations including those carried out during the Occupation of Japan, is today the National Institute for Educational Policy Research (国立教育政策研究所 Kokuritsu kyōiku seisaku kenkyūjo). It is not that Ōgushi did not believe in the superiority of "Nihon minzoku" as a spiritual superior entity and standard bearer of morality. The problem is whether it was "racial" or whether it was "national" in the sense of the content of demographic vessel that comprised the "nationals" of Japan. "Nihon kokumin" referred to Japanese nationals as subjects of Japan who possessed Japan's nationality -- a raceless status, hence embracing Japanese who were territorially "Interiorites" (affiliates of prefectural Interior registers), "Taiwanese" (affiliates of Taiwan registers), or "Chosenese" (affiliates of Chōsen registers). "Nihon minzoku" referred to nationals as an ethnic collectivity, idealized as "Yamato minzoku" -- the romantic reference to the collective ethnic nation. "Nihon" was a state, consisting of "nationals" (kokumin) belonging by law to various territories, within which there were various kinds of people -- all of whom were supposed to aspire to being proud members of Japan's ethnic nation (Nihon minzoku) idealized as the Yamato ethnic nation (Yamato minzoku). The United States also classified "race" two ways, one in the narrow "color" sense, another in the broader anthropological sense of "minzoku" -- as defined, for example, in the thick "Dictionary of Races or Peoples" published by the United States government in 1910 for purposes of racial classification on passenger manifests of vessels arriving from foreign ports. The introduction of this guidebook, which became a standard in other countries that also required captains to disclose information on arriving passengers, spoke of "five grand divisions . . . the Caucasian, Ethiopian, Mongolian, Malay, and American, or, as familiarly called, the white, black, yellow, brown, and red races . . . made upon physical or somatological grounds" -- and "the subdivisions of these into a multitude of smaller 'races' is made largely on a linguistic basis" (see Race boxes at ports of entry). Such "racial" thinking clearly inspired ethnologists and others in Japan, who did not resist viewing humans "racially" -- whether in the "five grand divisions" or in terms of the smaller "races" diffferentiated mainly by language. Dower, referring to a report published Doak on "ethnic nation" and "race"Kevin M. Doak takes Dower to task almost reflexively representing "minzoku" as "race" rather than "ethnic nation".
Shimazu on Japan's 1919 "racial equality proposal"RESUME definitions of "race" that were prevalent in "white" America, Britain, Australia, and "white" Canada" (minzoku) -- such legal differentiation ese and Chosenese as affiliates under its territorial -- "used the term " -- and intended to say "national equality" (minzoku rather than "that the English term "race" was more likely to refer to what in Japanese was called "jinshu" than than to what in Japanese was called "minzoku". But she sho) also appears to be attributed to , for athe charter of the Legdisi, where Japan proposed that the League of Nationals understood Wilson to have been calling for racial quality, he says, they were dissillugot the impression that Wilson meant racial equality, Japanese understood that Wilson meant "racial equality" that its Japanese translation "which became the equivalent of ", the notion that "nationalism" is historically more closely associated takes Dower to task for 大串 兎代夫(おおぐし とよお、1903年1月19日 - 1967年1月3日)は、日本の法学者、国家学者。元名城大学総長。従四位勲三等瑞宝章。国民精神文化研究所では三羽烏の1人と呼ばれた。 大串兎代夫 日本民族世界観の確立 文藝春秋 東京:文藝春秋社 第20巻、第1号 昭和16年 印刷 昭和17年1月1日 発行 ( 新年号、特集:大東亜戦争完遂のために Ōgushi Toyoo Nihon minzoku sekaikan no kakuritsu [Establishment of Japanese national worldview] Bungei shunjū Tokyo: Bungei Shunjū Sha Volume 20, Number 1 New year issue, Special feature: For the completion of the Great East Asia War KOSHO TWO ISSUES 文芸春秋20巻1号 状態良 保田與重郎 横光利一 1,000円 保田與重郎 横光利一、 文芸春秋社、 昭17 文芸春秋20巻11号 状態良 横光 間宮茂輔 1,000円 横光 間宮茂輔、 文芸春秋社、 昭17 文芸春秋 第20巻第1号 大東亜戦争完遂のために、創刊20周年記念原稿当選発表、他 菊池寛、大串兎代夫、河田嗣郎、ホールヴエック、他著、 文藝春秋社、 昭17 文芸春秋 昭17年2月(20巻2号)東亜共栄圏確立の原理・座談会、南方資源論(金子鷹之助)、大串兎代夫、牧野富太郎、・・・ 史録書房 1,000円 花房満三郎編、 文芸春秋社、 昭17 A5版216頁 ヤケ 文芸春秋 昭17年4月(20巻4号)翼賛議会確立のために(大串兎代夫他)、日独同盟の哲学的基礎(デュルクハイム)、斎・・・ 史録書房 1,000円 花房満三郎編、 文芸春秋社、 昭17 A5版216頁 ヤケ 文芸春秋 昭17年5月(20巻5号)経済再編成と転廃業・座談会、藤沢親雄、大串兎代夫、藤田徳太郎、横光利一他 史録書房 1,000円 花房満三郎編、 文芸春秋社、 昭17 A5版208頁 ヤケ 文芸春秋 昭17年11月(20巻11号)十二月八日の反省(大串兎代夫)他 史録書房 800円 藤沢閑二編、 文芸春秋社、 昭17 A5版208頁 ヤケ 背痛 Dower 1993In the first endnote to the eighth essay -- "Race, Language, and War in Two cultures" (pages 257-285) -- Dower refers the reader to War Without Mercy for "full annotations" and remarks that "Here I have sharpened the focus on racial language in comparative perspective" (page 285). His "Sources and Credits" at the end of the book state that the was originally presented under the title "Group Defamation and the American-Japanese War" at an April 1988 conference (page 356). Dower's characterization of "Yamato minzoku" as an essentially "racist" notion is very strong (page 273, underscoring mine).
Both "race" in the more physical sense of "jinshu" ("yellow" in opposition to "white") -- and "race" in the more historical, linguistic, cultural, and spiritual sense of "minzoku" (referring to "racioethnic nations") -- were, to be sure, powerful metaphors globally. That "blood nationalism" in the Empire of Japan was at times "potent" is undeniable. That it was "exceptionally" potent, when potent, strikes me as untrue. Dower would have benefited from the writings of Kevin M. Doak, but Doak did not critically address Dower's excess racialization of "minzoku" until 1995 (see Kevin Doak on "minzoku" and "kokumin" for reviews of Doak's writing). If he saw Doak's 1995 article, and noticed Doak's remarks, he chose to ignore them in his 1999 book (see next). Dower 1999Dower on "kokumin" and 1950 Nationality LawDower, in Embracing Defeat, makes this statement regarding the choice for "kokumin" rather than "jinmin" to represent "the people" in the draft constitution presented the Japanese government by the Supreme Commander for the Allied Forces, General Headquarters (GHQ/SCAP) (Dower 1999, pages 381-382, italics his, underscoring mine).
A dozen pages later, Dower wraps up his discussion of the "jinmin" versus "kokumin" issue like this (Dower 1999, page 394, italics his, underscoring mine).
Koseki, a specialist on constitutional law, qualifies the "jinmin" versus "kokumin" issue somewhat differently, in the Japan Quarterly article referred to by Dower (Satō 1988, page 236, underscoring mine)
Koseki goes on to say this about the 1950 Nationality Law (Satō 1988, page 236, underscoring mine).
Koseki then speculates about Satō's ulterior motive in favoring "kokumin" as the term defining "the people" in the 1947 Constitution in relation to "former colonial subjects from Korea and Taiwan" (Satō 1988, page 236, underscoring mine).
Chung's version of postwar legal history is clearly inspired by Dower's version, and Dower's version is clearly inspired by Koseki and others who have omitted a number of facts that suggest that the concerns of Japanese legalists like Satō were considerably broader than concerns with the contemporary or future treatment of Taiwanese and Chosenese. I will enumerate the serious omissions in their arguments after clarifying a few details. The legalist Matsumoto Jōji (松本烝治 1877-1954), a former director of the Legislative Bureau, was the cabinet minister responsible for coordinating the revision of the Constitution during the early phases of the drafting of the new Constitution. Satō Tatsuo (佐藤達夫 1904-1974), a career bureaucrat, had served in the Ministry of Interior before joining the Legislative Bureau (法制局 Hōseikyoku), an Cabinet office established under the 1890 Constitution. In 1962, the bureau was renamed the Cabinet Legislation Bureau(内閣法制局 Naikaku Hōseikyoku) to differentiate it from the legislative bureaus that each of the two houses of parliament had established under the 1947 Constitution. Satō became the vice director of the bureau in March 1946 when the Japanese government began nationalizing GHQ's draft constitution. Satō and a number of other legalists did, in fact, strongly oppose the manner in which the GHQ draft had stipulated, regarding "Rights and Duties of the People" (Chapter III), that "All natural persons are equal before the law" (Article XIII) and "Aliens shall be entitled to the equal protection of law" (Article XVI). This would seem to conflict with the preamble, which began "We, the Japanese People, acting through our duly elected represntatives in the National Diet . . . do proclaim the sovereignty of the people's will and do ordain and establish this Constitution . . . ."It would seem that "the Japanese People" who would "proclaim the sovereignty of the people's will" could not possibly have included people other than "Japanese" as a matter of nationality. The terms "natural persons" would include all people, both Japanese (persons who possess Japan's nationality), and "aliens" (persons who do not possess Japan's nationality. The 1899 Nationality Law very clearly spoke of "Japanese" in terms "nationality". The terms "equal before the law" and "equal protection of law" do not mean "equal" as a matter of status or treatment based on status. Why, in any event, should "natural persons" and "aliens" be included in a list of "rights and duties" regarding "the People" defined as those who possess sovereignty? Would this have meant that all natural persons in Japan, including all Japanese and all aliens, were to have the same rights and duties? Whatever Satō et al personally felt about the Emperor as the symbolic head of state, in relation to the sovereign People of Japan, as legalists they were also responsible for ensuring that the new Constitution was compatible with conventional distinctions between people who are Japanese and not Japanese in terms of their nationality, meaning their formal affiliation with the state -- i.e., "kokumin". All countries in the world, including the United States, have made distinctions between nationals and non-nationals. Both "jinimin" and "kokumin" had been legal terms in Japanese law since the Meiji period. The term "jinmin" (人民) was commonly used to refer to the "people" of the state that were parties to international treaties, but it was also used in the 1872 Family Regster Law -- as was "kokumin" (国民 national) -- as was "shinmin" (臣民 subject) -- to refer to those who to be registered as the "people" or "nationals" or "subjects" of Japan. In other words, from the start of the Meiji period, these terms, in reference to Japan, referred to "Nihonjin" (日本人 Nihonjin) -- the term used in a number of other status laws, including the 1873 proclamation concerning status changes in alliances of marriage or adoption between Japanese and aliens. The 1890 Constitution spoke of "shimin" -- but personal status provisions in the 1890 Civil Code -- which satisfied the constitution's requirement for a statute that defined the conditions for being a "subject" -- spoke of "national status" [status of national] (国民分限 kokumin bungen), which defined "status of [being] Nihonjin" (日本人の分限 Nihonjin no bungen), inspired by phrasing familiar since as early as the 1873 marriage and adoption proclamation. The 1890 Rules of Laws also spoke of "national status" -- which became "nationality" (国籍 kokuseki) in the 1899 Nationality Law. The 1890 Civil Code had been promulgated but not enforced, and the government decided, when rewriting the civil code and rules of laws, to establish the "national status" provisions as an independent "nationality" law. The 1899 Nationality Law, though also intended to satisfy the call in the 1890 Constitution for a statute determining the requirements of being a subject, also spoke only of "nationality" in terms of "being Japanese" at time of birth or gain or loss later in life. Being Japanese at time of birth was based on either jus sanguinis or jus soli standards, depending on the conditions of birth, and jus sanguinis standards were either patrilineal or matrilineal standards depending on the conditions of birth. Neither race nor ethnicity were issues. Some Japanese laws spoke of "subjects" and others spoke of "nationals". There is no doubt that all people regarded as possessing Japan's nationality were regarded as "emperor (loyal) affiliates" or "subjects" (shinmin) in relation to the sovereign Emperor, as people whose allegiance belonged to him -- and as "nation affiliates" or "nationals" as members of the state's demographic nation. It is true that at the time Japan's constitution was being revised that the sinific term "jinmin" was used by communists and others to mean "the people" as "citizens" (公民 kōmin) as a political collectivity, rather than as "nationals" (国民 kokumin), which implied that they were bound to the state. At the same time, the meaning of "the people" in American law was different than its meaning in "British law" -- as noted by Koseki (see above), and also at considerable length by Inoue (Inoue 1991, especially pages 185-186). My point would be that where Inoue and others dwell too much on the terminological issue as one involving the status of the Emperor in relation to the people of Japan, Dower -- and many others before him and following him -- have ignored the more fundamental civil status issues, and mischaracterized the meaning of "kokumin" historically, in their rush to characterize the revisions reflected in the 1947 Constitution and the 1950 Nationality Law as "racist". In point of fact: At the , and revision in order to advance the notion that "race" and "racism" inspired the "linguistic subterfuge" (Chang: ) unreasonably were different and the meaning of "the people law and "the people" in British law as absolute Article specifically referred to aliens in the new Constitution. GHQ/SCAP's attempt to The manner in which GHQ/SCAP attempted to do so was rather clumsy -- in view of the conflicts between the meanings of "natural persons" and "the People" in rather sloppy GHQ/SCAP draft. In fact, "natural persons" would have embraced all people, but "the People" would have embraced only those who were considered as "nationals" in Japanese domestic law, or as "citizens" in US domestic law. All states in principle differentiate between their own nationals and aliens. Apart from Satō's and To be continued. "kokumin" and 1950 Nationality LawForthcoming. "mixed-blood children" and nationalityForthcoming.
Chung's second contentiondoes two things of great interest. First, she bases her statement mainly on Dower's version of the adoption of "kokumin" in 1947 Constitution and its implications for the 1950 Nationality Law, which is flawed by its omission of a number of important facts, but especially the following. . Then, having earlier contended that before the 1950 Nationality Law the differentiation of "former colonial subjects" had been based on race or ethnicity, she contends that now discrimination was based on "citizenship status" -- her Americanism for status as a "national" of Japan if one one possesses its nationality.Chung's implication that, in the end, "citizenship status" in the 1950 Nationality Law was also ultimately based on race and ethnicity is also consist with Dower's claim that the "racist" use of "kokumin" inspired the "discriminatory" 1950 Nationality Law (John W. Dower, Embracing Defeat: Japan in the Wake of World War II, New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1999, page 394, italics his, underscoring mine).
A number of writers have contended that the treatment of Taiwanese and Chosenese by the Japanese government, if not also by GHQ/SCAP, was "racist". Their classification as "non-Japanese" by SCAP for purposes of repatriation, their ineligibility to vote or run for office under the election law when revised in 1945, their treatment as "aliens" under the 1947 Alien Registration Order, and of course their "deprivation" of Japanese nationality in 1952 were motivated by "racism". Forthcoming. "Koreans in Japan" constitute an extremely mixed and ethnically diverse population of people in Japan, whether (1) the population of Special Permanent Resident (SPR) aliens of one or another Korean nationality who are legally linked to the former colonial population of Chosenese which lost its Japanese nationality in 1952, (2) the somewhat larger population of Korean aliens including, in addition to SPRs, migrants the Republic of Korea (practically all) and the Democratic People's Republic of Korea (very few), or (3) the much larger population of people including, in addition to Korean aliens, Japanese and others who might be regarded as partly "Korean" on racioethnic rather than nationality grounds. Special Permanent Resident is a status of residence based on separation from (loss of) Japanese nationality in 1952, accorded people who have been continuously residing in Japan since 2 September 1945 and descendents who were born in Japan and have continously resided in Japan. The SPR status is held by aliens representing about fifty (50) nationalities. The vast majority are Koreans, practically all of them nationals of the Republic of Korea (ROK) or "Kankoku", while the rest are nationals of "Chōsen" referring to the territory that was "liberated" from Japan in 1945 and formally separated from Japan in 1952. Some "Chōsen" Koreans claim to be citizens of the Democratic People's Republic of Korea (DPRK) but Japan does not recognize its nationality. SPR status is not, in any event, based on present nationality, but on having lost Japanese nationality on 28 April 1952 due to the effectuation of the San Francisco Peace Treaty, or having been born in Japan to such a person since this date -- with the additional qualification that one has continuously been domiciled in Japan since 2 September 1945 or since birth after this date. after this dateNationality status is not, in any event, a qualification for SPR, while other but Japan does not recognize DPRK neither Japan nor ROK recognizes DPRK nationality. To my knowledge, none of the few aliens in Japan who entered the country as migrants from DPRK qualify as SPR, ROK nor Japan recognizecalled "Kita Chōsen) Japan does not recognize, called "Kita Chōsen" in most separated from Japan after World War which, when separated from Japan following World War II, represents the nationality linked with "Korean" nationality that Chosense, as Japanese nationals, were supposed to recover when Chō, a territory of Japan resulting from Japan's annexation of the Empire of Korea in 1910, was formally separated from Japan in 1952.of the former Japanese territory of Chōsen different nats are aliens whose status of residence in Japan The vast majority of Special Permanent Residents in Japan are Koreans of one or another Korean nationality, and some non-Korean SPRs are their nationality being a strictly civil, non-racial status.SPRs come in about fifty differenty nationalitys The first two populations are "Korean" "one-drop blood" or Korean status who qualify as Speci (whether These flaws stem from the desire of the author's to turn "Koreans in Japan" -- who consinto an "Overseas Korean" race box that essentially RESUME DISARMING "RACE" BIASED READERS Your introduction, where you raise the questions you seek to answer, is the place where you can most effectively disarm readers who might think your purpose is to "apologize" for what Japan "did" (or rather "didn't") do. You have to stress that no matter what Japan "did" or "didn't" do -- in the absence of lateral agreement (with either the Allied Powers or with or or the other or both Korean states) -- would have been "unilateral" -- whether a purely "political" or "legal" or "moral" or "racial" issue -- mindful that ANY legal solution in the ABSENCE of an INTERNATIONAL agreement HAD TO BE based on Japan's domestic laws. Japan had basically two options -- (1) "choice", which would have required the creation of municipal registers in Japan -- or (2) alienization (denationalization in the form of "recovery" of Chosen -- i.e., "Korea", not ROK or DPRK -- nationality status when Chosen was separated from Japan) followed by naturalization (if, as an alien, one wanted to revert to Japanese nationality. Both the "choice" and "naturalization" options could have been facilitated by laws enabling qualified persons to create registers (or naturalize, and create registers) on the basis of a notification procedure. MULTILATERAL UNILATERALITY Again, any action on Japan's part, in the absence of a lateral (bilateral or multilateral) agreement, would have been unilateral on Japan's part. Yet what Japan did was not exactly "unilateral" -- given the manner in which it resolved such issues with ROC, and given the manner in which such issues were negotiated with ROK -- BEFORE the 19 April 1952 notification concerning loss of nationality. The question, then, what legal conventions in regional (but especially Japan's) affiliation laws, and what political conditions, affected Japan's "moral choice". Assuming that the right "moral choice" would have been to offer a "nationality choice" -- you have to show that to have provided such a "nationality choice" was not as easy as it sounds, considering the laws of the land and the political battles that would have to have been fought and won in the Diet to change the laws of the land in any timely manner. And to have given a choice within the framework of contemporary laws wo uld have engendered political battles elsewhere, in Japan and between Japan and the Korean states. ROK, however, recognized (as it had to, being a sovereign state) that Japan's nationality was its domestic call, since all states have the right to define their own nationality. ROK was only interested in trying to get Japan to (1) recognize its claim to have rights to regard Chosenese as its nationals, or at least to recognize that ROK's domestic laws (namely, it's 1948 Nationality Law, would determine whether Chosenese would qualify as ROK nationals). And it wanted either "national treatment" or special permanent residence status for its nationals in Japan. KIM DONG-JO All this is clear from what has been written about the first round of ROK-Japan talks -- including, most importantly, what was written by Kim Dong-Jo in his 1986 book "Kan-Nichi no wakai" (titled in English "Korea-Japan Reconciliation"). Kim participated in the 1st, 4th, and 7th rounds -- and was ROK's head of delegation in the 7th and last (1964-1965) round -- and one of the two ROK plenipotentiaries who signed the 1965 normalization treaty and status agreement. He gives three pages to the "nationality problem" and I will translate them tomorrow. His statement sparkles with clarity. Kim, of course, was born, raised, and totally educated in Japan inclusive of Chosen -- schooled in both Keijo and Fukuoka -- a Ministry of Health bureaucrat in Kyoto at the time Japan surrendered -- then a careerist in ROK's Ministry of Foreign Affairs. You can't get better than that. And nothing he omits from his story, that I can think of, is ammunition for the argument that Japan commit ted a moral sin in (1) denationalization Chosenese and Taiwanese as of 28 April 1952 -- and, simultaneously, creating a legal status that evolved into the 1966 Kyotei status for qualified ROK nationals, the 1982 Tokurei status for others, and the 1991 Tokubetsu Eiju status for all. What Japan did was consistent with what ROK and Japan essentially agreed to in the 1st round of talks. If Price is insistent that you speak of "construction", then I would swap the term for "de-construct" by which you mean "un-constsruct" what had already been formally "constructed". In other words, go along with him to a point, but in the service of your own argument. It is thought terminating argument to claim that everything is "constructed". Sure, laws are "constructed" just as buildings are "constructed". But if you are faced with an existing building, and want to remodel it, or replace it with a new building, then you need to rebuild part of it, or tear it down. Even ROK did not entirely tear down the received Japanese territory of Chosen. The USAMGIK insisted that things be done in an orderly fashion, and that meant keeping a lot of things going as they were. 35 years (45 Actually, Price is wrong about "construction". The Allied Powers, and the Japanese government, were faced with the problem of having to "deconstruct" statuses which had already been constructed, and recognized, under international law and domestic law as practiced after the 1910 annexation. That was the whole object of "liberation" and the reduction of the Empire of Japan to "Japan" as redefined for Occupation (i.e., legal) purposes. The legal empire of Japan had to be "deconstructed" or "unconstructed" legally. It is a no-brainer to argue that ALL parties -- SCAP, the Japanese government, Korean organizations in Japan, and Korean organizations elsewhere, including of course ROK and DRPK when they were established -- were "racialist" in the racioethnic "nationalist" sense of "minzoku" considerations. It is vastly more difficult to show that the actual "deconstruction" of the territorial statuses which had been treated as cause for Japanese nationality proceeded in a gen erally orderly and "lawful" manner, from the viewpoint of all state parties (including SCAP representing the Allied Powers). ROK (and presumably also DPRK) did not, of course, RECOGNIZE that "Korea" had ever legally become "Chosen", hence "Koreans" had ever truly become "Chosenese", hence "Koreans" remained "Koreans" and had actually been "Koreans" in the eyes of ROK's 1919 provisional government. |